Homo academicus
and the analysis of intellectual fields
Moreno Pestaña Jose Luis
Professor
University of Cadiz
Abstract
In Homo academics, Bourdieu proposed an
epistemological reflection that is of interest to both further researches on
the object itself as well as the practice of sociology in general. Secondly, he proposed a map of
the university world in France, the various forms of capital that organise it
and the most customary types of career paths. Despite the national basis of his
analysis, Bourdieu insisted that it could be extended beyond France. Thirdly, he offered an
explanation of a historical event that spilled over from the university campus,
yet one in which the university played a major role; the uprising of May ‘68
showed how a historic event that partially destabilised the social order
occurred. Epistemological, structural and historical orders - these are the
angles from which Homo academicus shall be read. This paper addresses Homo academicus’
scientific insights into the academic and intellectual world.
Keywords
Sociology
of intellectual field, Pierre Bourdieu, Epistemology of Social Sciences.
Homo
academicus* was a difficult book for Pierre Bourdieu to write,
although he did not work on it alone. The research was conducted together
with Yvette Delsault (2002: 229-230), a very close collaborator at the
time. Bourdieu offered to list Delsault as the book’s co-author, but she turned
the offer down because she disagreed with its final tone, considering it too "violent"
and "male" to associate her name with. Yet, Delsault
recognised that the book was produced with enormous methodological precaution,
as Bourdieu insisted in the interview between them. Homo academicus is a work on two fronts: human, all too human, on
the one hand, and scientifically well controlled, on the other. The first
aspect is not analysed here; this would require a sociology of the sociology of
the academic world advocated by Bourdieu, regarding whether or not the academic
world is strongly indebted to the author’s position and trajectory and whether
or not the methodological tools and concepts Bourdieu used are best suited for
tackling this undertaking. This paper addresses the second aspect, i.e.
Bourdieu's scientific insights into the academic and intellectual world.
Turning
empirical individuals into epistemic ones
Bourdieu explained that analysing reality from a
sociological point of view means reformulating it according to certain relevant
parameters; this allows all individuals to be classified according to identical
criteria. Of course, there are many ways to classify individuals in an
analytical scientific framework. Bourdieu took this scientific pluralism for
granted in the process of constructing names in sociology. These names are not
like ordinary ones; they do not designate empirical
individuals with their complex personalities that are difficult to sift
through in a series of predicates. A scientific name designates a series of
properties that produce effects in a field. Bourdieu thus called agents epistemic individuals. The difference
between empirical and epistemic individuals is helpful in understanding how
scientific concepts are distinguished from the epithets of ordinary language.
Two empirical individuals are separated by proper nouns that provide no
information about their differences. A scientific concept groups together
diverse empirical individuals that share a series of features that make them
equivalent from that point of view as agents within a plane of reality. The
scientific concept renames the empirical individual and turns it into an
effective agent in a social space, i.e., an epistemic individual.
Society in general and the academic world in
particular teem with classifications, starting with university posts, which
consecrate individuals as professors or lecturers. Yet, behind these common
nouns are individuals with different properties: one may have a genuine
scientific influence, while another is a university administrator and a third
spends his time on journalistic interventions. In reality, the common appellation
encompasses very different properties and interests in divergent social worlds.
They have the same “names”, but have different competences and devote
themselves to different realities (HA, 63). These names are not trivial - they
sustain social hierarchies, e.g., it is assumed that professors know more than
assistant lecturers do or that researchers are guided by scientific
requirements: perhaps they are guided by the demands of local university policy
and spend more time on social contacts than reading and publishing. Thus, a
scientific name allows reality to be viewed differently from that which current
classifications permit. Furthermore, these classifications are in conflict,
since each agent seeks to impose those that best suit his or her own interests.
In the case of academia, Bourdieu suggests that the lack of shared references -
and cacophonous multiplication of different parameters of judgement - for
ranking merit acts as a shared defence system that allows subjects to ignore
their true positions by resorting to the system of classification that best
allows them to save face in terms of themselves and others (HA, 104).
Does this mean that epistemic individuals allow us to
see a societal reality that would be obscured in everyday life? Bourdieu’s
answer is yes and no. The positive response is provided by the very subjects
under analysis, who sometimes recognise planes of their existence in the
sociologist’s explanations. These usually go unnoticed, since individuals are
oriented, without too much reflexive distance, towards everyday urgencies (HA,
38). If he had paused at this point in his argument, Bourdieu would have
considered that his scientific construction would reveal the truth of the
world, with the sole reservation being that we must not confuse what is
revealed by the analysis with the agents’ conscious intention.
So where is the awareness that the sociological
perspective is a construct that, as such, does not attempt to mirror the nature
of society? At two levels: first, epistemic individuals become continuous
discrete properties and separate features that in reality are not distributed
so precisely. In other words, epistemic individuals do not overlap completely
with empirical individuals, as if the latter were a repeatable and interchangeable
example of the kind contained in the sociological concept. Bourdieu (HA, 40-41)
does not indicate it, but he comes very close to one of the central ideas of
Jean-Claude Passeron’s epistemology (2006: 89-123). Sociological names are
logical mixes that designate a series of general traits[1]
as common nouns on the one hand, yet on the other, are only valuable - if they
are not to become empirically empty concepts - when they refer to a series of
research operations situated in time and space[2].
In short, the names imposed by sociologists - in their epistemic renaming of
empirical individuals - are not the only legitimate ones.
In addition, sociologists, especially when studying
their own universe, must take precautions to clarify the three types of bias that
inevitably accompany their research. This clarification is inexhaustible and therefore never reaches the
point in which it becomes possible to contemplate all partial perspectives of
the world without taking part in any. First, because of the biases from
their own social and scientific trajectories, which Bourdieu (2001, 2004)
attempted to finish analysing in the last book he published and his course on
science; second, because of the assumptions implicit in the concepts employed,
e.g., someone who confuses social determination with a lack of lucidity (the
agent as a mere carrier of structures) cannot understand the concept of habitus, which starts from the thesis
that we have variable degrees of understanding of our determinations and
partial means of calculation for following, countering or opposing our social
determinations. Therefore, one assumption (a philosophical idea of freedom: freedom as absolute non-conditioning) lies
behind many of the criticisms levelled by those who do not understand the philosophical
assumptions of the notion of habitus
and believe that it functions as a tyrannical clamp that strangles all
creativity and all lucidity in subjects. Third, researchers should renounce the
use of science to influence the scientific world and promote their own
interests. This is the case, said Bourdieu (HA, 29-30), of a work by Raymond
Boudon in which he denounced French celebrities and flattered international
(mainly American) ones, without revealing what was at stake (his own stock
would rise if his vision of the good and the bad rankings triumphed) or
stopping for an instant to examine empirically whether reality resisted his
analysis (something that Bourdieu believed happens when, e.g., the researchers
least valued by French scientists are those with the greatest impact on the
very international Citation Index).
Distances and proximities in the field of academic
power
Faculties
in conflict
Two kinds of capital (economic and cultural) organise
the field of power. University professors are closer to the latter: the
dominated pole in the field of power. This pole is also internally divided
between the sectors that depend the most on the culture market (e.g., writers
and journalists) and those who, like academics, have institutional support. The
distances between the two sectors depend on their historical circumstances.
Their separation was at a peak from the late nineteenth century - a period in
which the gap between academic and political power grew - until the period
between the two world wars in the twentieth century. After that, growth in the
student population made it necessary to recruit less academic teachers from the
cultural and journalistic professions. In fact, Bourdieu insisted that each
period could be studied according to the relationships that existed between the
academic and cultural worlds, whose indicators could be found in comparing the
social and academic origins of the populations of the two territories, the
steps between one field and another, the meeting places and the way in which
the two populations conceive their success[3].
The division between the economic and cultural capital
that structures the field of power is reproduced within each faculty and among
them all. That is, from one minute to the next, Bourdieu seems to reason as if
each situation contained the same principles of differentiation as those with
which the sociologist constructs his object...and nothing more. Bourdieu was a
great admirer of Gottfried W. Leibniz, who argued in Monadologie (§ 56) that the whole universe is expressed within each
substance and that a mirror of the whole of reality can be contemplated by
looking into it. Therefore, if we had an infinite perspective and knew all the
circumstances surrounding a concrete being, we could predict the direction of
his or her future trajectory. Reality would lose its historical character and
become the monotonous reiteration of identical principles of differentiation
regardless of time, space or place and when such differentiations do not occur,
it would be because our knowledge of reality is incomplete. Undoubtedly,
Bourdieu could have argued that he is only logically developing the principles
he chose for constructing the object of study, although other perspectives
would be possible. As noted above, this stance would be consistent with the
reading here of his epistemological introduction[4].
Returning to Bourdieu's analysis, the field of the
university reproduces the field of power and thus, science faculties are
dominated from the temporal (political and economic) viewpoint by the medicine
and law faculties, i.e., the faculties closest to the field of economic power tout court; when the hierarchy is
scientific, the relationships are reversed. The faculties of arts lie halfway
between the two.
Bourdieu shows how each position recruits the human types needed to maintain
its stability. Institutions are ways of generating similar habitus. The faculty of medicine transmits knowledge, but also a
way of life in accordance with its dominant values, which reveals the Catholic
preponderance in the corps. Law professors come mostly from the bourgeoisie and
tend to accumulate posts at the university, in politics and even in business.
In contrast, regardless of whether they come from the middle or working classes
or the university arena itself, the professors tend to consecrate themselves to
the institution to which they owe their upward social mobility. In short, those
who invest the most in scientific life tend to celibacy, whereas university
students who go into politics or the world of capital are accompanied by an
extended family as a sign of their social integration.
Furthermore, each faculty has its own definition of research
activities. This is one of the points that demonstrates the empirical
fruitfulness of Bourdieu's analytical model. The coexistence of different
definitions of research is a classic topic in the sociology of knowledge. As
Randall Collins (2000: 523-569, 874-877) explained, research in the sciences
with one sole paradigm allows collective concentration on a problem (the
"rapid-discovery sciences"). Research goes hand in hand with
technological innovations, which become the criteria of good scientific work.
Mathematical notation allowed a common language to be created and to some
extent resolved the ever delicate question of how to translate empirical
results linguistically. Teamwork became possible and the technological
concentration of activity allowed for a relative indifference to theoretical
issues. At sometimes there is a vivid theoretical awareness of the work of
scientific teams, while at others, intellectual work is reduced to
retrospectively producing the results obtained with technologies.
Bourdieu
believed that this model, which originates in the natural sciences, has invaded
all scientific activity and homogenised very dissimilar realities, which each
faculty redefines. Many researchers are merely patrons who spend their lives
chasing funding - and cultivating social capital – so that others may conduct
research. Thus, scientific life is more like managing a clientele and the
connections with the political and economic networks that allow it to be
maintained. The logic of social capital prevails over research problems. This
is the profile of the tolerant patron, heir to social capital networks
(families, universities), who masks his or her lack of effective commitment to
science with politically and theoretically antidogmatic professions (firmly
defining something controversial must be avoided when social capital is being
cultivated) and is mainly concerned about the quality of his or her contacts
(be they students or places where resources can be found). The students’
scientific and intellectual education is less important than the promise of a
managed career. Therefore, to be able to enter these recruitment networks, one
needs to show that one shares the group’s values: social origin - forming part
of a good family – is one criterion and enthusiastic docility towards group
integration is another (HA, 79). Above all in medicine and law, co-optation does not promote scientific skills, but
rather global modes of being, habits. These faculties, which recruit by
implicit curricula, are more socially selective than those in which the
required competencies are more formalised and not transmitted through familiar
pedagogical action, such as is
the case of the sciences.[5] The various faculties and
different poles within them (more spiritual or temporal) confront the dilemma
of either producing socially integrated agents to perform established functions
or being guided by the logic of scientific rationality. Social responsibility
and scientific responsibility face off in a zero sum game. The higher one is,
the lower the other. It goes without saying that Bourdieu’s position lies far from the radical critiques of the power of
science that, based on diverse ideological sources (ranging from the extreme
left to the extreme right), were inflated in May ‘68 and configured the
postmodern nebulae towards which Bourdieu was always enormous hostile.
The
powers and the arts
As an example of conflict between the two types of
power, Bourdieu focused on the faculties of arts in
Bourdieu did not explain how the population studied in
this extremely hierachised universe could survive in the lower echelons. The
basic assumption is none other than the existence of an academic society in which
those on the bottom and those on top pursue the same thing, according to
identical criteria. Those who do not register on the
dominant academic hierarchies, have no relevant information to offer the
Bourdieu analysis, except the testimony of their lack of success, which amounts
to the same thing. These discourses of rationalisation prevent the
existence of a shared evaluation system that would require everyone to know his
or her true position. But perhaps one might think that Bourdieu did not
contemplate the plural forms of life at the university.
Insofar as institutional power is concerned,
Bourdieu’s methodological option is reasonable: the Vice-Chancellor of the
University of Paris has more influence than a head of a department and it is absurd to bestow the properties of both with
the same weight in a study. If the question is intellectual reputation, it also
cannot be denied that it is concentrated in those who cross a certain threshold
(e.g., more than five mentions in the Citation
Index).[6] Another question is whether scientific prestige can
be measured in this manner, as Bourdieu believes. Is having peer recognition -
which is what the Citation Index reflects
- for a certain time, equivalent to productive intellectual work? On this point
Bourdieu comes very close to Randall Collins (2000: 85-87), who believes that
only a series of individuals (those who access the centre of the attention
space) representing a position (between three and six faculties are in
conflict, otherwise there is no possibility of common points of discussion)
monopolise intellectual attention in a period. The rest can be discarded,
although Collins acknowledges that several intellectual giants were largely
unrecognised in their day (Moreno Pestaña, 2009). Whether or not one believes
that the networks of intellectual productivity are being confused with networks
of notoriety in contemporary times – which is a little more than dubious[7] - it is true that Bourdieu provided a very limited
map of academic and intellectual passions and that another selection of the
population - and another theoretical framework - would provide a very different
view of university life and its agents’ institutional and intellectual libido.
How does purely academic power function, according to
Bourdieu’s model? By occupying positions that determine other subjects’ access
to certain posts. The individuals most gifted with university capital, who are
often poorly esteemed as scientists, establish their clienteles by exchanging
services with one another. Often these relationships begin at the École Normale Supérieure, the centre of
socialisation of the elite French university, which does not exist in other
countries. Age differentiates holders of academic power, since attaining
positions of power takes time, respect for the logical order of succession and
refraining from haste. Competition, Bourdieu insists, is the condition of the
order, since those who compete accept a shared value and moreover, are the
dominant poles that regulate competition.
How do the dominant poles regulate university
competition? By toying with hopes of and access times to posts. To achieve
this, the possibilities of access must be restricted, so that the agents can
form reasonable, circumscribed expectations (a scant possibility attracts
almost no one) that are – very importantly - relatively vague, so that the
patron can manipulate the contenders (the more contenders, the more power for
the patron). The contenders are in a position of infantilisation and
subordination to a power without defined rules, which thus places them in a
state of permanent anxiety, in addition to inciting them to submit even further
to the patron in order to unseat other contenders.
University patrons – there are those who
scientifically train their disciples and help them publish, but they are in the
minority - must move between two extremes in which the sources of their power
may dry up. On the one hand, they must not place too many roadblocks to their
students’ independence if they do not want to lose the power of attraction, yet
on the other hand, they cannot throw their students into adult university life
too early, unless they want the work of infantilisation not to produce its
inculcatory effect, which would consequently lead to an autonomous competitor disputing
their clientele. University patrons - no matter how poor they may be as
scientific mentors - attract the brightest students, who are also the closest,
socially speaking. The circle of reproduction is closed: professors tend to be
recruited from those who understand the game, pick suitable thesis topics and
patrons, know how to wait during their professional careers (assuming the
dependence and even humiliations of infantilisation, with its consequent
restrictions on other areas of life), are able to wait (because they have the
financial, family and institutional means to do so) and know how to provide
their degree tutor intellectual, yet above all social proof that they will be
worthy disciples.
This is the university habitus in the locus closest to power and with it comes
intellectual conservatism, the enemy of everything aside from academic
"reliability" (le sérieux),
i.e., the practical consensus that allows an academic and intellectual
equilibrium between the different poles of power. Institutional networks,
moreover, require that time be invested in them through the supervision of
theses, attendance at conferences, membership on examining boards,
participation in journals and on top of this, invitations proffered to
colleagues and the acceptance of their invitations. This allows the group time
to bestow institutional recognition, but obviously prevents attending to
intellectual output, a condition of scientific recognition. Academic power is
thus a time-based power that occupies a space that, in principle, was conceived
for intellectual output. Aware of its imposture, academic power never stops
perceiving itself as fragile and hence, its occasional aggressiveness towards
scientific creators.
Bourdieu explains that blind adherence to an academic
institution comes largely from the social properties of those who populate it.
Recruited from among the petty bourgeoisie with no cultural capital other than
that provided by the institution, satisfied with their status, these producers’
favourite output are manuals of synthesis that serve on the one hand to
reinforce social capital networks - by recognising "contributions"
from colleagues - and on the other, to provide an outlet for the output needed
to triumph in competitive exams. It is thus a question of an intellectual
output that allows one to rise in the hierarchy of professors while it is being
produced, not to mention the lucrative economic benefits generated.
At the time and place Bourdieu studied, the university
locus closest to the scientific pole tended to be in new disciplines
(sociology, ethnology) or marginal ones, i.e., those in which there were fewer
controls on access and fewer routines that inculcated practices. Their institutional settings were the Collège de France and École des Hautes Études en Sciences Sociales.
The low teaching load
allowed for scientific exploration and the establishment of their own work
plans, in accordance with the dominant scientific debates. Disputes over the
attention space, as Randall Collins would say, motivate agents within a setting
that allows very few consecrations. Bourdieu considered that this risky game
can only be played by a population that, confronted with the population of
professors, appears to be more favoured, socially speaking (HA, 143). This
confirms a "law" (which Bourdieu holds in great theoretical esteem)
that restricts the propensity to risk to the disposition of more capital, since
scientists and intellectual creators do not receive a great deal of
institutional reward (Bourdieu points out the weakness at the university of
Althusser, Foucault and Barthes at that time).
Does Bourdieu’s description have general sociological
value or is it restricted to the period he studied? As a work plan it is not
useless. Jumping to another time and place, the historical sociology of the
Hellenistic schools formulated by Michel Foucault (2001: 111-112) offers an
interesting clue for linking social origin with the mode of practicing
philosophy and/or religion. Hellenistic schools spread the practices of
reflecting on life itself that the Athenian world reserved for a certain elite.
Obviously, there was a cultural and economic threshold below which it was
highly unlikely - if not impossible - to partake in intellectual life. Once
that threshold was crossed, two poles could be distinguished: one, often
occupied by people of humble origin, focussed on ritual practices of a
religious kind in which sectarian affiliation and the observance of worship
took precedence over the work of individual transformation and philosophical
output; the other pole abounded with the wealthy classes at a greater distance
from ritual practices; these classes were more creative in subjective
modification and cultural creation. Bourdieu would say that the process
described by Foucault has a more general value: the dominated classes acquire
more security in better coded and more closely defined cultural settings; the
dominant classes can afford a more relaxed relationship with the culture
because of their cultural capital and a precociously acquired sense of orientation.
However, as Foucault insisted and any moderately complex historical analysis
would show, it would be a mistake to turn a certain trend into an ideal
dogmatic type, which would presume the rigidity of the lower middle classes
through dogma and religiosity and the complex capabilities of the culturally
and economically privileged classes through philosophy and creativity. The
Epicureans were originally made up of the popular classes; they ostentatiously
distanced themselves from religion and produced a sophisticated philosophy.
Moreover, the Hellenistic schools’ philosophical reflections were often
accompanied by very intense religious and ritual practices. Similarly, mass
organisations (monasteries, boarding schools, academic ghettos, “Stalinist”
communist parties) composed of permanent mass rites capable of homogenising
their populations’ social properties have contributed as much, if not more
intellectual creativity than bohemia has.
Thus, while Bourdieu’s trend shows its heuristic value
in other fields, it should be counterpoised, as he himself demanded (HA 149),
against more complex and varied studies on the relationships among social
properties, academic position and cultural output. This would require, we
insist once again, another kind of selection of the population studied
(tailored in Homo academicus to
institutional consecration and peer recognition) and of course, deeper and
broader studies on how cultural life is connected to an individual’s social
resources.
A complicity functions in the background between the
two powers - scientific and the university - despite their separation. Firstly,
because they structure the field of the possible on the basis of the
justification that the other’s weaknesses provides. University power is
reinforced in the compulsive and often intellectually inane search for
innovation that characterises many cultural and scientific vanguards. Cultural
producers, in turn, are justified in everything that is not academic and have
their counter model in a court-like university life and reiterative
intellectual output.
Beyond the two
powers lies scientific and cultural creation. Intellectual recognition does not
immediately ensure the creative quality of a work. This is measured by its
ability to retain its interest as we move away from the cultural space and time
segment in which it was produced. Intellectual reputation is measured in the
short term; creativity requires connecting to problems defined by an
intellectual field with a long history. Often, worldly prestige is merely an
offering in step with the times. With its great potential for the sociology of
intellectuals, the heuristic value of the distinction formulated by Bourdieu
(1998: 236) between short-cycle products (which meet the expectations set...and
conclude with them) and
long-cycle products (which subsist at the time of emergence and continue to
produce effects even when the cultural contexts in which they were conceived
disappears) can only be assumed with these caveats. Peer recognition has its brilliant potential (being
recognised by the intellectually consecrated), but also its possible downside
(becoming mere reproducers of an ideology with scientific signs that respond to
a non-scientific demand). Bourdieu showed that this is happening more and more
due to the growing influence of the consecration of journalism in intellectual
life. Scientific appearances allow the conquest of an audience made up of
students and professors alert to cultural trends and - given their low level of
expertise - incapable of comprehending the nuances and demands of scientific
work. To satisfy them, researchers assume an essayistic style and share with
journalism a repulsion for academic pedantry. The conquest of an audience for
such products increasingly requires the complicity of cultural journalism and
the world of publishing. In these conditions, dialogue with the intellectual
tradition and scientific vanguard - conditions for genuinely creative work in
the humanities - can be counterproductive to connecting with broad audiences.
In turn, the colonisation of scientific life does not
proceed solely from the culture market, but also from the administrative world.
Commissioned research requires developing skills to attract public and private
funds and the corporate governance of research groups, as well as adapting to
experts who evaluate the results, lines of work and methodologies.
In short, the university campus is the locus of
competition between plural powers. Because the fields need to deal with the
outside world, the pressure of external powers on them redefines their borders:
demographic changes require retaining or encouraging the order of succession;
the culture industry imposes scientific models and the administrative
management of the industrial research practices of intellectual output.
The sociological explanation of the event
After the map, the narration. Although universal
values are claimed or
identified with causes beyond its medium, a university always acts according to
the logic of its own field and its options are always and inevitably signs that
guide its colleagues and contenders. May ‘68 was the result of changes in the
academic world that largely arose from the crisis caused by the booming number
of university students and consequently lecturers during the 1960s. This boom
did not produce identical effects across all disciplines, for the simple reason
that there was no unified higher education area and each local market had its
own hierarchies and values (HA, 180). The effects, therefore, require a
description of circumstances, which demonstrates what was mentioned above:
Bourdieu's hypothesis about society does not run roughshod over its
peculiarities, even though they contain complications - the existence of
hierarchies different from those perceived when the social field is viewed from
the top - regarding the most schematic versions of Bourdieu’s view of the
social space.
The less firmly established academic disciplines had
fewer staff reserves adapted to the institutional order. The pace of succession
ceased to function as envisaged and two types of actors entered the game.
First, individuals who had followed the orthodox route of access and discovered that their promotion no longer
gave them what they had hoped for: many saw their careers stall and did not
have access to the posts they expected. Second were the individuals,
particularly in less academic subjects, who were appointed without the
corresponding training and resented the impositions of the established order.
Thus, the complicities were ruptured by two different and incompatible criteria: the defence of
ancient privileges and those who contested the phases and rhythms that used to
set the pace of access thereto. Neither of these groups suggested the programme
Bourdieu wanted: “An order in which recruitment and
professional advancement depend only upon the criteria of productivity and
educational and scientific efficiency” (HA, 205).
The crisis
in the education system affected society as a whole, firstly, because of
education’s increasingly important role in reproducing the class system and
secondly, because of the distance between the academics’ hopes -
nourished by an earlier system of demands and rewards – and the effective
rewards, fewer than expected, which created an atmosphere of widespread revolt.
The frustration was greater among those from dominant groups, although the
effects of the devaluation of diplomas were more pronounced among working-class
students. However, the latter do not judge the world in the same way that the
dominant class does, firstly,
because they have more tolerance for frustration and secondly, because the
working classes’ local markets, which do not all function from the
perspective of the écoles, still
value what statistical analysis may consider an objective devaluation (HA,
214). In any case, the crisis of the offspring of the bourgeoisie found echoes
among fractions of the middle classes with similar feelings and even
among young workers or farmers frustrated by the meagre fruits of primary or
secondary education. Although it had different effects according to class, the
crisis of diplomas unified heterogeneous populations.[8]
Multiple dynamics came together in the faculties of
arts: the new disciplines offered there were the particular refuge of, first, young bourgeoisies with low
educational achievements and high aspirations, and, second, middle-class
students who could not get into other degree programmes and had little social
capital to enable them to capitalise on their diplomas and professors appointed
rapidly without the mandatory training in university submission. Agents from
different fields found themselves in homologous positions, but the distance between the son of a teacher and that of an
intellectual who has only precarious access to higher education is enormous.
These misleading identifications only exist during a crisis; afterwards, when
the social order is re-imposed, each pursues its respective, often conflicting
objectives. Crises produce emotionally dense communities capable of bringing
together people who would ordinarily be separated (HA, 229), something that the
theory of rational action is incapable of grasping.
Communication between the distant populations that
characterised the crisis provided Bourdieu with a rich sociological
phenomenology of revolutionary experience. First, existences were synchronised
between the dominant and dominated classes, which play in different worlds.
Since the dominant class plays in more fields than the dominated class does,
the latter tend to be more sincere, more deeply committed to their life
choices. Those on top above, however, must always be true to more complex
loyalties, which requires them to lead "parallel lives". When the end
of the crisis reveals this multiplicity of references, the sense of betrayal
will overwhelm the dominated class.
Secondly, and related to this, the actors’ representation dissolves societal
complexity and sums it up in two camps: us and them, the rulers and the ruled,
the basic outline of all Zhdanovisms. The crisis brutally economises symbolic
differentiations and retranslates them into political terms. The internal
dynamics of social worlds, which can radically separate two individuals, are
abolished, bringing together socially heterogeneous agents and separating
other, much closer ones. Thirdly, far from being a mere swindle, a
revolutionary situation dissolves the usual relationship with the world: the
past does not seem to weigh (dissolved in a euphoric ritual interaction), nor
does the future impose a calculating conduct on the present. Therefore, the
revolutionary experience does not appeal to everyone equally. Those who are
most firmly established view it as the Apocalypse and a relapse into barbarism,
while those who are the least integrated - no matter how young or least
benefited by the system - tend to sympathise with the opportunities it
presents. Fourthly, the eruption of revolutionary situations favours
those who are versed in managing political events and know how to semantically
condense widely dispersed positions. In the end, despite the claim of
spontaneity, May ’68 favoured those who were trained in the far-left political
apparatus, which had lacked an audience until then. Like many analysts,
Bourdieu found the aggressive, disrespectful style of the leaders of May ’68 to
be part of the culture of the dominant “rabble” that according to Perry
Anderson (1998: 86) controls capitalism today.
Conclusion
A reading of Bourdieu's work reveals its enormous
power of inspiration, which is always accompanied by several reservations: at
the epistemological level, it
recognises the legitimate plurality of scientific approaches, which follows
logically from his differentiation between the empirical and epistemic
individual, and at the structural level, the theory of homology between social
worlds serves as a heuristic tool and not a mechanical metaphysic that
strangles empirical work, e.g., believing that the world at the Parisian
intellectual summit serves to reveal the realities of
university, intellectual or scientific life.
At the historical level, Bourdieu explained the crisis
as the situational conjunction of different dynamics, capable of producing
novelties at different levels of persistence. As a model it is flawless. But of
course, it may be objected to if the academic world as he studied it (at the
heights of full professors) helps us understand the events of May ‘68.
Bibliography
Anderson, Perry. 1998. The Origins of Postmodernity,
London, Verso.
Baranger, Denis. 2009: “Para el estudio de los campos
universitarios : Pierre Bourdieu y la construcción del objeto en Homo
Academicus”, Pensamiento Universitario, nº 12.
Bourdieu, Pierre. 1980: Le sens pratique, Paris, Minuit.
—(1984) Homo
academicus, Paris, Minuit.
—(1998): Les
règles de l’art. Genèse et structure du champ littéraire, Paris, Seuil.
—(2001): Science
de la science et réflexivité, Paris, Raisons d’agir.
—(2004): Esquisse pour une auto-analyse,
Paris, Raisons d’agir.
Delsault, Yvette.
2002: “Pierre Bourdieu et Yvette Delsault entretien. Sur l’esprit de la
recherché”, Delsault Yvette, Rivière Marie Christine, Bibliographie des
travaux de Pierre Bourdieu sui d’un entretien sur l’esprit de la recherche,
Pantin, Le Temps des Cerises.
Collins, Randall.
2000: The sociology of philosophies. A
global theory of intellectual change, Cambridge, Massachussetts and London,
Harvard University Press.
Foucault, Michel.
2001: L’herméneutique du sujet. Cours au
Collègue de France. 1981-1982, París, Gallimard-Seuil.
Gruel, Louis. 2004: La
rébellion de 68. Une relecture sociologique, Rennes, PUR.
Moreno
Pestaña, Jose Luis. 2009. “Pour une sociologie de l’échec
intellectual”, EspacesTemps.net,
Textuel, http://espacestemps.net/document7864.html.
Passeron, Jean
Claude. (2006): Le raisonnement sociologique. Un espace non poppérien de
l’argumentation. Paris,
Albin Michel.
* Text written as part of R+D
project FFI2010-
[1] Agents with capital
structure dominated by academic power.
[2]
And in that sense, they serve as proper nouns: these concepts to analyse those
subjects, after having analysed them along these
guidelines.
[3]According
to a study cited by Alain Girard, writers usually have a more charismatic
vision of success, whereas professors attribute it to their teachers and
families.
[4]
In any case, readers have a right to doubt the constant resort to homologies
(every reality has internal divisions that overlap with the internal divisions
of others) and wonder whether sociological work does not serve as an example
for certain metaphysics. In that case, the criticisms levelled against Passeron
Jean-Claude (2006: 310-311) without mentioning him by name would be completely
justified. See a balanced, critical consideration of the use of the Análisis
de Correspondencias Múltiples in Homo academicus in Baranger (2009:
71-72).
[5] Bourdieu’s
passion for sociology, which is the enemy of inspired essayism, derived from a
belief in a shared scientific rationality, but also from an egalitarian social
commitment to those who could only resort to their academic efforts to produce
discourses on reality. See Bourdieu (1980: 11).
[6] Based on
the population of university professors in Paris, Bourdieu (HA, 101) retained
those who have at least two of the properties set out in detail as follows: as
far as university power is concerned, membership in the Institute de France, the board of examiners for the agrégation, the École Normale Supérieure and the Universities Consultative
Committee. As far as scientific power is concerned, membership in the CNRS
commission between 1963 and 1967. And as regards scientific power: more than
five mentions in the Citation Index.
[7]
Bourdieu is aware of the problem, as shown by footnote 8 on p. 104 of Homo
academicus, although he decides not to pay much attention to it.
[8] Louis Gruel (2004) has criticised Bourdieu’s
explicative model, insisting first, on the inexistence of the devaluation of
diplomas, second, on the university world’s poor grasp of the rebellion and
third, on the nature of the crisis as
the intergenerational transmission of a universal culture.
View Counter: Abstract | 549 | times, and
ACADEMIA | eISSN: 2241-1402 | Higher Education Policy Network
Pasithee | Library & Information Center | University of Patras